Ergodic without atoms implies completely conservative?Hopf decompostion for diffeomorphismsShift invariant measures that are(n't) convex combinations of ergodic measuresRecurrence for sets of finite measure on infinite measure spaceThe relations between conservative part and conservativityMarkov operators and existence of ergodic measuresNatural extensions in ergodic theory / Measurability questionIs there a complete Riemannian manifold with infinite volume whose the time-one map of the geodesic flow is recurrent?A Rokhlin lemma with a prescribed height function?Free ergodic probability measure-preserving actions of the free groupA generalized Furstenberg's $times p,times q$-conjecture

Ergodic without atoms implies completely conservative?


Hopf decompostion for diffeomorphismsShift invariant measures that are(n't) convex combinations of ergodic measuresRecurrence for sets of finite measure on infinite measure spaceThe relations between conservative part and conservativityMarkov operators and existence of ergodic measuresNatural extensions in ergodic theory / Measurability questionIs there a complete Riemannian manifold with infinite volume whose the time-one map of the geodesic flow is recurrent?A Rokhlin lemma with a prescribed height function?Free ergodic probability measure-preserving actions of the free groupA generalized Furstenberg's $times p,times q$-conjecture













5












$begingroup$


I am currently trying to learn Patterson-Sullivan theory, but I am getting stuck on basic questions about ergodic theory. Here is one of them, given as an exercise in one of the texts I am trying to read. If you need wider context, the text (in French) is here, with the relevant question towards the bottom of page 17 (next-to-last sentence of the long paragraph).



Let ($Omega$, $Gamma$, $mu$) be a dynamical system satisfying the following assumptions:




  • $Omega$ is a Hausdorff, locally compact and $sigma$-compact topological space;


  • $Gamma$ is a countable group acting on $Omega$;


  • $mu$ is a Radon measure on $Omega$ that is quasi-invariant by $Gamma$ (for every $g in Gamma$, $g_* mu$ is absolutely continuous with respect to $mu$).

Let us recall some definitions:



  • a subset $W subset Omega$ is called wandering if, for $mu$-almost all $w in W$, the intersection of the orbit $Gamma w$ with $W$ is finite;

  • we say that the system is completely conservative if $Omega$ has no wandering subsets of positive measure;

  • we say that the system is completely dissipative if $Omega$ has some wandering subset $W$ such that $Omega = bigcup_g in Gamma g W$.

Statement to prove: If the system is ergodic and the measure $mu$ does not have any atoms, then the system is completely conservative.



Even though it is supposed to be an easy exercise ("on vérifie aisément que..."), I am at a loss. I have found a partial proof, that works only if you can assume that the set $W$ introduced in the proof is closed. Unfortunately, I have no idea whether it is true, in general, that every completely dissipative dynamical system is generated by a closed wandering set. Can someone give me a proof of this last statement, or find some other way to fix my proof presented below?



In fact, I have remarkably little intuition about what "completely dissipative" actually means. I am tempted to think that a completely dissipative action should in particular be properly discontinuous, but apparently this is false (though I have never seen an actual counterexample). I would be very happy if I could find, somewhere, an arsenal of examples and counterexamples of completely dissipative and completely conservative systems, that is sufficiently well-stocked to forge an intuition about these properties and to be able to test whether some reasonable-sounding statement is actually true.



The partial proof: Let $Omega = Omega_C sqcup Omega_D$ be the Hopf decomposition of $Omega$, i.e. a partition of $Omega$ into two $Gamma$-invariant subsets such that $Omega_C$ is completely conservative and $Omega_D$ is completely dissipative. Since the system is ergodic, they cannot both have positive measure: this means that $Omega$ is either completely conservative or completely dissipative. By contradiction, assume the latter: let $W subset Omega$ be a wandering subset such that
$$Omega = bigcup_g in Gamma g W.$$
Note that the set
$$x in W mid Gamma x cap W text is finite cap operatornameSupp(mu)$$
has the same (positive) measure as $W$, hence is nonempty. Let $x_0$ be any point in this set. Let $F := g in Gamma mid g x_0 in W $; this is a finite set by construction.



Since $x_0 in operatornameSupp(mu)$, every neighborhood of $x_0$ has positive measure; on the other hand, since the measure is Radon and without atoms, any point has neighborhoods of arbitrarily small measure. Let $U$ be some neighborhood of $x_0$ such that for every $g in F$, we have $mu(g U) < fracmu(W)# F$. We can also assume (provided that $W$ is closed!) that for all $g notin F$, the image $g U$ is disjoint from $W$. Then consider the set $X := bigcup_g in Gamma g U$:



  • this set is $Gamma$-invariant by construction;

  • it has positive measure by construction;

  • its complement $Omega setminus X$ contains in particular $W setminus X$, the complement of $W cap X$ in $W$. But by construction, the intersection $W cap X$ is contained in $bigcup_g in F g U$, so that we have
    $$mu(W cap X) leq sum_g in F mu(g U) < mu(W).$$
    Hence the complement $W setminus X$, and hence also the complement $Omega setminus X$, has positive measure. But these three properties of the set $X$ contradict ergodicity, QED.









share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$
















    5












    $begingroup$


    I am currently trying to learn Patterson-Sullivan theory, but I am getting stuck on basic questions about ergodic theory. Here is one of them, given as an exercise in one of the texts I am trying to read. If you need wider context, the text (in French) is here, with the relevant question towards the bottom of page 17 (next-to-last sentence of the long paragraph).



    Let ($Omega$, $Gamma$, $mu$) be a dynamical system satisfying the following assumptions:




    • $Omega$ is a Hausdorff, locally compact and $sigma$-compact topological space;


    • $Gamma$ is a countable group acting on $Omega$;


    • $mu$ is a Radon measure on $Omega$ that is quasi-invariant by $Gamma$ (for every $g in Gamma$, $g_* mu$ is absolutely continuous with respect to $mu$).

    Let us recall some definitions:



    • a subset $W subset Omega$ is called wandering if, for $mu$-almost all $w in W$, the intersection of the orbit $Gamma w$ with $W$ is finite;

    • we say that the system is completely conservative if $Omega$ has no wandering subsets of positive measure;

    • we say that the system is completely dissipative if $Omega$ has some wandering subset $W$ such that $Omega = bigcup_g in Gamma g W$.

    Statement to prove: If the system is ergodic and the measure $mu$ does not have any atoms, then the system is completely conservative.



    Even though it is supposed to be an easy exercise ("on vérifie aisément que..."), I am at a loss. I have found a partial proof, that works only if you can assume that the set $W$ introduced in the proof is closed. Unfortunately, I have no idea whether it is true, in general, that every completely dissipative dynamical system is generated by a closed wandering set. Can someone give me a proof of this last statement, or find some other way to fix my proof presented below?



    In fact, I have remarkably little intuition about what "completely dissipative" actually means. I am tempted to think that a completely dissipative action should in particular be properly discontinuous, but apparently this is false (though I have never seen an actual counterexample). I would be very happy if I could find, somewhere, an arsenal of examples and counterexamples of completely dissipative and completely conservative systems, that is sufficiently well-stocked to forge an intuition about these properties and to be able to test whether some reasonable-sounding statement is actually true.



    The partial proof: Let $Omega = Omega_C sqcup Omega_D$ be the Hopf decomposition of $Omega$, i.e. a partition of $Omega$ into two $Gamma$-invariant subsets such that $Omega_C$ is completely conservative and $Omega_D$ is completely dissipative. Since the system is ergodic, they cannot both have positive measure: this means that $Omega$ is either completely conservative or completely dissipative. By contradiction, assume the latter: let $W subset Omega$ be a wandering subset such that
    $$Omega = bigcup_g in Gamma g W.$$
    Note that the set
    $$x in W mid Gamma x cap W text is finite cap operatornameSupp(mu)$$
    has the same (positive) measure as $W$, hence is nonempty. Let $x_0$ be any point in this set. Let $F := g in Gamma mid g x_0 in W $; this is a finite set by construction.



    Since $x_0 in operatornameSupp(mu)$, every neighborhood of $x_0$ has positive measure; on the other hand, since the measure is Radon and without atoms, any point has neighborhoods of arbitrarily small measure. Let $U$ be some neighborhood of $x_0$ such that for every $g in F$, we have $mu(g U) < fracmu(W)# F$. We can also assume (provided that $W$ is closed!) that for all $g notin F$, the image $g U$ is disjoint from $W$. Then consider the set $X := bigcup_g in Gamma g U$:



    • this set is $Gamma$-invariant by construction;

    • it has positive measure by construction;

    • its complement $Omega setminus X$ contains in particular $W setminus X$, the complement of $W cap X$ in $W$. But by construction, the intersection $W cap X$ is contained in $bigcup_g in F g U$, so that we have
      $$mu(W cap X) leq sum_g in F mu(g U) < mu(W).$$
      Hence the complement $W setminus X$, and hence also the complement $Omega setminus X$, has positive measure. But these three properties of the set $X$ contradict ergodicity, QED.









    share|cite|improve this question









    $endgroup$














      5












      5








      5





      $begingroup$


      I am currently trying to learn Patterson-Sullivan theory, but I am getting stuck on basic questions about ergodic theory. Here is one of them, given as an exercise in one of the texts I am trying to read. If you need wider context, the text (in French) is here, with the relevant question towards the bottom of page 17 (next-to-last sentence of the long paragraph).



      Let ($Omega$, $Gamma$, $mu$) be a dynamical system satisfying the following assumptions:




      • $Omega$ is a Hausdorff, locally compact and $sigma$-compact topological space;


      • $Gamma$ is a countable group acting on $Omega$;


      • $mu$ is a Radon measure on $Omega$ that is quasi-invariant by $Gamma$ (for every $g in Gamma$, $g_* mu$ is absolutely continuous with respect to $mu$).

      Let us recall some definitions:



      • a subset $W subset Omega$ is called wandering if, for $mu$-almost all $w in W$, the intersection of the orbit $Gamma w$ with $W$ is finite;

      • we say that the system is completely conservative if $Omega$ has no wandering subsets of positive measure;

      • we say that the system is completely dissipative if $Omega$ has some wandering subset $W$ such that $Omega = bigcup_g in Gamma g W$.

      Statement to prove: If the system is ergodic and the measure $mu$ does not have any atoms, then the system is completely conservative.



      Even though it is supposed to be an easy exercise ("on vérifie aisément que..."), I am at a loss. I have found a partial proof, that works only if you can assume that the set $W$ introduced in the proof is closed. Unfortunately, I have no idea whether it is true, in general, that every completely dissipative dynamical system is generated by a closed wandering set. Can someone give me a proof of this last statement, or find some other way to fix my proof presented below?



      In fact, I have remarkably little intuition about what "completely dissipative" actually means. I am tempted to think that a completely dissipative action should in particular be properly discontinuous, but apparently this is false (though I have never seen an actual counterexample). I would be very happy if I could find, somewhere, an arsenal of examples and counterexamples of completely dissipative and completely conservative systems, that is sufficiently well-stocked to forge an intuition about these properties and to be able to test whether some reasonable-sounding statement is actually true.



      The partial proof: Let $Omega = Omega_C sqcup Omega_D$ be the Hopf decomposition of $Omega$, i.e. a partition of $Omega$ into two $Gamma$-invariant subsets such that $Omega_C$ is completely conservative and $Omega_D$ is completely dissipative. Since the system is ergodic, they cannot both have positive measure: this means that $Omega$ is either completely conservative or completely dissipative. By contradiction, assume the latter: let $W subset Omega$ be a wandering subset such that
      $$Omega = bigcup_g in Gamma g W.$$
      Note that the set
      $$x in W mid Gamma x cap W text is finite cap operatornameSupp(mu)$$
      has the same (positive) measure as $W$, hence is nonempty. Let $x_0$ be any point in this set. Let $F := g in Gamma mid g x_0 in W $; this is a finite set by construction.



      Since $x_0 in operatornameSupp(mu)$, every neighborhood of $x_0$ has positive measure; on the other hand, since the measure is Radon and without atoms, any point has neighborhoods of arbitrarily small measure. Let $U$ be some neighborhood of $x_0$ such that for every $g in F$, we have $mu(g U) < fracmu(W)# F$. We can also assume (provided that $W$ is closed!) that for all $g notin F$, the image $g U$ is disjoint from $W$. Then consider the set $X := bigcup_g in Gamma g U$:



      • this set is $Gamma$-invariant by construction;

      • it has positive measure by construction;

      • its complement $Omega setminus X$ contains in particular $W setminus X$, the complement of $W cap X$ in $W$. But by construction, the intersection $W cap X$ is contained in $bigcup_g in F g U$, so that we have
        $$mu(W cap X) leq sum_g in F mu(g U) < mu(W).$$
        Hence the complement $W setminus X$, and hence also the complement $Omega setminus X$, has positive measure. But these three properties of the set $X$ contradict ergodicity, QED.









      share|cite|improve this question









      $endgroup$




      I am currently trying to learn Patterson-Sullivan theory, but I am getting stuck on basic questions about ergodic theory. Here is one of them, given as an exercise in one of the texts I am trying to read. If you need wider context, the text (in French) is here, with the relevant question towards the bottom of page 17 (next-to-last sentence of the long paragraph).



      Let ($Omega$, $Gamma$, $mu$) be a dynamical system satisfying the following assumptions:




      • $Omega$ is a Hausdorff, locally compact and $sigma$-compact topological space;


      • $Gamma$ is a countable group acting on $Omega$;


      • $mu$ is a Radon measure on $Omega$ that is quasi-invariant by $Gamma$ (for every $g in Gamma$, $g_* mu$ is absolutely continuous with respect to $mu$).

      Let us recall some definitions:



      • a subset $W subset Omega$ is called wandering if, for $mu$-almost all $w in W$, the intersection of the orbit $Gamma w$ with $W$ is finite;

      • we say that the system is completely conservative if $Omega$ has no wandering subsets of positive measure;

      • we say that the system is completely dissipative if $Omega$ has some wandering subset $W$ such that $Omega = bigcup_g in Gamma g W$.

      Statement to prove: If the system is ergodic and the measure $mu$ does not have any atoms, then the system is completely conservative.



      Even though it is supposed to be an easy exercise ("on vérifie aisément que..."), I am at a loss. I have found a partial proof, that works only if you can assume that the set $W$ introduced in the proof is closed. Unfortunately, I have no idea whether it is true, in general, that every completely dissipative dynamical system is generated by a closed wandering set. Can someone give me a proof of this last statement, or find some other way to fix my proof presented below?



      In fact, I have remarkably little intuition about what "completely dissipative" actually means. I am tempted to think that a completely dissipative action should in particular be properly discontinuous, but apparently this is false (though I have never seen an actual counterexample). I would be very happy if I could find, somewhere, an arsenal of examples and counterexamples of completely dissipative and completely conservative systems, that is sufficiently well-stocked to forge an intuition about these properties and to be able to test whether some reasonable-sounding statement is actually true.



      The partial proof: Let $Omega = Omega_C sqcup Omega_D$ be the Hopf decomposition of $Omega$, i.e. a partition of $Omega$ into two $Gamma$-invariant subsets such that $Omega_C$ is completely conservative and $Omega_D$ is completely dissipative. Since the system is ergodic, they cannot both have positive measure: this means that $Omega$ is either completely conservative or completely dissipative. By contradiction, assume the latter: let $W subset Omega$ be a wandering subset such that
      $$Omega = bigcup_g in Gamma g W.$$
      Note that the set
      $$x in W mid Gamma x cap W text is finite cap operatornameSupp(mu)$$
      has the same (positive) measure as $W$, hence is nonempty. Let $x_0$ be any point in this set. Let $F := g in Gamma mid g x_0 in W $; this is a finite set by construction.



      Since $x_0 in operatornameSupp(mu)$, every neighborhood of $x_0$ has positive measure; on the other hand, since the measure is Radon and without atoms, any point has neighborhoods of arbitrarily small measure. Let $U$ be some neighborhood of $x_0$ such that for every $g in F$, we have $mu(g U) < fracmu(W)# F$. We can also assume (provided that $W$ is closed!) that for all $g notin F$, the image $g U$ is disjoint from $W$. Then consider the set $X := bigcup_g in Gamma g U$:



      • this set is $Gamma$-invariant by construction;

      • it has positive measure by construction;

      • its complement $Omega setminus X$ contains in particular $W setminus X$, the complement of $W cap X$ in $W$. But by construction, the intersection $W cap X$ is contained in $bigcup_g in F g U$, so that we have
        $$mu(W cap X) leq sum_g in F mu(g U) < mu(W).$$
        Hence the complement $W setminus X$, and hence also the complement $Omega setminus X$, has positive measure. But these three properties of the set $X$ contradict ergodicity, QED.






      ds.dynamical-systems ergodic-theory






      share|cite|improve this question













      share|cite|improve this question











      share|cite|improve this question




      share|cite|improve this question










      asked 5 hours ago









      Ilia SmilgaIlia Smilga

      399211




      399211




















          2 Answers
          2






          active

          oldest

          votes


















          4












          $begingroup$

          The desired statement is entirely measure-theoretic, so it's not really necessary to think about the topology of $X$. By standard descriptive set theory, there exists a Borel linear ordering $preceq$ on $X$. (This means that the graph of $preceq$ is a Borel subset of $X times X$.)



          Suppose toward a contradiction that $mu$ is nonatomic and the $Gamma$-action is ergodic but that there exists a wandering set $W$ of positive measure. Without loss of generality we may assume that the intersection of every $Gamma$-orbit with $W$ is finite. The ordering $preceq$ restricts to a linear ordering on each $Gamma$-orbit. If a $Gamma$-orbit $mathcalO$ intersects $W$ then $mathcalO cap W$ is nonempty and finite, so that the $preceq$-least element of $mathcalO cap W$ is well-defined. Since $preceq$ is Borel, the set $V$ consisting of the $preceq$-least element of each such set $mathcalO cap W$ is Borel. The set $V$ contains at most one point from each $Gamma$-orbit. Since $W subseteq bigcup_gamma in Gamma V$ and $mu$ is $Gamma$-quasi-invariant it follows that $mu(V) > 0$.



          Since $mu$ is nonatomic, there exists a Borel set $V_1 subseteq V$ such that if we write $V_2 = V setminus V_1$ then $min(mu(V_1),mu(V_2)) > 0$. Let $widetildeV_j = bigcup_gamma in Gamma gamma V_j$. For each $j in 1,2$ the set $widetildeV_j$ is $Gamma$-invariant and since $widetildeV_j$ contains $V_j$ we have $mu(widetildeV_j) > 0$. By ergodicity it follows that $mu(X setminus widetildeV_j) = 0$ for each $j in 1,2$.



          We claim that $widetildeV_1$ and $widetildeV_2$ are pairwise disjoint, which will lead to the contradiction $$0 < mu(widetildeV_2) leq mu(X setminus widetildeV_1) =0$$



          We will establish the claim by showing that that existence of $x in widetildeV_1 cap widetildeV_2$ leads to a further contradiction. Suppose that there exists such a point $x$. Then there exist $gamma_1,gamma_2 in Gamma$ with $gamma_1x in V_1$ and $gamma_2x in V_2$. Since $V_1 cap V_2 = emptyset$ we have $gamma_1x neq gamma_2x$. Since $gamma_1x = gamma_1gamma_2^-1gamma_2x$ we see that $gamma_1x$ and $gamma_2x$ are in the same $Gamma$-orbit. This cannot be the case since $gamma_1x$ and $gamma_2x$ are both elements of $V$ and $V$ contains at most one point from each $Gamma$-orbit.



          $mathbfResponse,, to ,,comment$



          The way to see that the set $V$ is Borel is to regard Borel sets as being defined by logical formulas. We say that a formula 'is Borel' if it defines a Borel subset of $X$. Countable existential quantifiers correspond to countable unions and not corresponds to complements. Thus these logical operations preserve the property of being a Borel formula.



          It is implicit in the hypotheses that $Gamma$ acts by Borel automorphisms. Since $preceq$ is Borel, it follows that the predicate $gamma x prec x$ is Borel for any $gamma in Gamma$. The set $V$ can be defined as $$x in W: (not exists)(gamma in Gamma)((gamma x in W) wedge (gamma x prec x))$$.






          share|cite|improve this answer











          $endgroup$












          • $begingroup$
            Nice proof, thank you! One point remains non-obvious for me: "Since $preceq$ is Borel, the set $V$ consisting of the $preceq$-least element of each such set $mathcalO cap W$ is Borel." Could you elaborate on this?
            $endgroup$
            – Ilia Smilga
            4 hours ago











          • $begingroup$
            I responded as an edit to the answer.
            $endgroup$
            – burtonpeterj
            3 hours ago


















          1












          $begingroup$

          First a general comment. Unfortunately, the categorical approach is completely missing in the way the measure theory is still taught nowadays, and the fact that there actually is only one "reasonable" purely non-atomic probability measure space (so called Lebesgue, Lebesgue--Rokhlin, or standard probability space) isomorphic to the unit interval endowed with the classical Lebesgue measure is not very widely known. Any Borel probability measure on a Polish space makes it a Lebesgue space, so that in particular all measure spaces one has to deal with in the Patterson theory are from this class.



          The definition of a wandering set you are using is a non-standard one. According to the usual definition a measurable set is wandering if all its translates are pairwise disjoint mod 0 (i.e., the intersection with almost any orbit consists of at most one point). However, it is very easy to see that the existence of a wandering set $W$ in your sense implies the existence of a "usual" wandering set $W'$. Namely, realize your measure space as the unit interval, and then for each orbit take the minimal point from its intersection with $W$. This operation is clearly measurable and provides you with a measurable set $W'subset W$, which is wandering in the usual sense.



          You are asking why ergodicity implies complete conservativity. The reason (with the right definition of wandering sets) is very simple: the union of the translates of any non-trivial subset of a wandering set is obviously a non-trivial invariant set. Actually, more generally, the union of the free discrete ergodic components of the action is precisely the dissipative part of the Hopf decomposition. See Kaimanovich for more details and Grigorchuk - Kaimanovich - Nagnibeda for various examples concerning the relationship between dissipativity and minimality of boundary actions.






          share|cite|improve this answer









          $endgroup$













            Your Answer








            StackExchange.ready(function()
            var channelOptions =
            tags: "".split(" "),
            id: "504"
            ;
            initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

            StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function()
            // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
            if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled)
            StackExchange.using("snippets", function()
            createEditor();
            );

            else
            createEditor();

            );

            function createEditor()
            StackExchange.prepareEditor(
            heartbeatType: 'answer',
            autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
            convertImagesToLinks: true,
            noModals: true,
            showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
            reputationToPostImages: 10,
            bindNavPrevention: true,
            postfix: "",
            imageUploader:
            brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
            contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
            allowUrls: true
            ,
            noCode: true, onDemand: true,
            discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
            ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
            );



            );













            draft saved

            draft discarded


















            StackExchange.ready(
            function ()
            StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmathoverflow.net%2fquestions%2f330010%2fergodic-without-atoms-implies-completely-conservative%23new-answer', 'question_page');

            );

            Post as a guest















            Required, but never shown

























            2 Answers
            2






            active

            oldest

            votes








            2 Answers
            2






            active

            oldest

            votes









            active

            oldest

            votes






            active

            oldest

            votes









            4












            $begingroup$

            The desired statement is entirely measure-theoretic, so it's not really necessary to think about the topology of $X$. By standard descriptive set theory, there exists a Borel linear ordering $preceq$ on $X$. (This means that the graph of $preceq$ is a Borel subset of $X times X$.)



            Suppose toward a contradiction that $mu$ is nonatomic and the $Gamma$-action is ergodic but that there exists a wandering set $W$ of positive measure. Without loss of generality we may assume that the intersection of every $Gamma$-orbit with $W$ is finite. The ordering $preceq$ restricts to a linear ordering on each $Gamma$-orbit. If a $Gamma$-orbit $mathcalO$ intersects $W$ then $mathcalO cap W$ is nonempty and finite, so that the $preceq$-least element of $mathcalO cap W$ is well-defined. Since $preceq$ is Borel, the set $V$ consisting of the $preceq$-least element of each such set $mathcalO cap W$ is Borel. The set $V$ contains at most one point from each $Gamma$-orbit. Since $W subseteq bigcup_gamma in Gamma V$ and $mu$ is $Gamma$-quasi-invariant it follows that $mu(V) > 0$.



            Since $mu$ is nonatomic, there exists a Borel set $V_1 subseteq V$ such that if we write $V_2 = V setminus V_1$ then $min(mu(V_1),mu(V_2)) > 0$. Let $widetildeV_j = bigcup_gamma in Gamma gamma V_j$. For each $j in 1,2$ the set $widetildeV_j$ is $Gamma$-invariant and since $widetildeV_j$ contains $V_j$ we have $mu(widetildeV_j) > 0$. By ergodicity it follows that $mu(X setminus widetildeV_j) = 0$ for each $j in 1,2$.



            We claim that $widetildeV_1$ and $widetildeV_2$ are pairwise disjoint, which will lead to the contradiction $$0 < mu(widetildeV_2) leq mu(X setminus widetildeV_1) =0$$



            We will establish the claim by showing that that existence of $x in widetildeV_1 cap widetildeV_2$ leads to a further contradiction. Suppose that there exists such a point $x$. Then there exist $gamma_1,gamma_2 in Gamma$ with $gamma_1x in V_1$ and $gamma_2x in V_2$. Since $V_1 cap V_2 = emptyset$ we have $gamma_1x neq gamma_2x$. Since $gamma_1x = gamma_1gamma_2^-1gamma_2x$ we see that $gamma_1x$ and $gamma_2x$ are in the same $Gamma$-orbit. This cannot be the case since $gamma_1x$ and $gamma_2x$ are both elements of $V$ and $V$ contains at most one point from each $Gamma$-orbit.



            $mathbfResponse,, to ,,comment$



            The way to see that the set $V$ is Borel is to regard Borel sets as being defined by logical formulas. We say that a formula 'is Borel' if it defines a Borel subset of $X$. Countable existential quantifiers correspond to countable unions and not corresponds to complements. Thus these logical operations preserve the property of being a Borel formula.



            It is implicit in the hypotheses that $Gamma$ acts by Borel automorphisms. Since $preceq$ is Borel, it follows that the predicate $gamma x prec x$ is Borel for any $gamma in Gamma$. The set $V$ can be defined as $$x in W: (not exists)(gamma in Gamma)((gamma x in W) wedge (gamma x prec x))$$.






            share|cite|improve this answer











            $endgroup$












            • $begingroup$
              Nice proof, thank you! One point remains non-obvious for me: "Since $preceq$ is Borel, the set $V$ consisting of the $preceq$-least element of each such set $mathcalO cap W$ is Borel." Could you elaborate on this?
              $endgroup$
              – Ilia Smilga
              4 hours ago











            • $begingroup$
              I responded as an edit to the answer.
              $endgroup$
              – burtonpeterj
              3 hours ago















            4












            $begingroup$

            The desired statement is entirely measure-theoretic, so it's not really necessary to think about the topology of $X$. By standard descriptive set theory, there exists a Borel linear ordering $preceq$ on $X$. (This means that the graph of $preceq$ is a Borel subset of $X times X$.)



            Suppose toward a contradiction that $mu$ is nonatomic and the $Gamma$-action is ergodic but that there exists a wandering set $W$ of positive measure. Without loss of generality we may assume that the intersection of every $Gamma$-orbit with $W$ is finite. The ordering $preceq$ restricts to a linear ordering on each $Gamma$-orbit. If a $Gamma$-orbit $mathcalO$ intersects $W$ then $mathcalO cap W$ is nonempty and finite, so that the $preceq$-least element of $mathcalO cap W$ is well-defined. Since $preceq$ is Borel, the set $V$ consisting of the $preceq$-least element of each such set $mathcalO cap W$ is Borel. The set $V$ contains at most one point from each $Gamma$-orbit. Since $W subseteq bigcup_gamma in Gamma V$ and $mu$ is $Gamma$-quasi-invariant it follows that $mu(V) > 0$.



            Since $mu$ is nonatomic, there exists a Borel set $V_1 subseteq V$ such that if we write $V_2 = V setminus V_1$ then $min(mu(V_1),mu(V_2)) > 0$. Let $widetildeV_j = bigcup_gamma in Gamma gamma V_j$. For each $j in 1,2$ the set $widetildeV_j$ is $Gamma$-invariant and since $widetildeV_j$ contains $V_j$ we have $mu(widetildeV_j) > 0$. By ergodicity it follows that $mu(X setminus widetildeV_j) = 0$ for each $j in 1,2$.



            We claim that $widetildeV_1$ and $widetildeV_2$ are pairwise disjoint, which will lead to the contradiction $$0 < mu(widetildeV_2) leq mu(X setminus widetildeV_1) =0$$



            We will establish the claim by showing that that existence of $x in widetildeV_1 cap widetildeV_2$ leads to a further contradiction. Suppose that there exists such a point $x$. Then there exist $gamma_1,gamma_2 in Gamma$ with $gamma_1x in V_1$ and $gamma_2x in V_2$. Since $V_1 cap V_2 = emptyset$ we have $gamma_1x neq gamma_2x$. Since $gamma_1x = gamma_1gamma_2^-1gamma_2x$ we see that $gamma_1x$ and $gamma_2x$ are in the same $Gamma$-orbit. This cannot be the case since $gamma_1x$ and $gamma_2x$ are both elements of $V$ and $V$ contains at most one point from each $Gamma$-orbit.



            $mathbfResponse,, to ,,comment$



            The way to see that the set $V$ is Borel is to regard Borel sets as being defined by logical formulas. We say that a formula 'is Borel' if it defines a Borel subset of $X$. Countable existential quantifiers correspond to countable unions and not corresponds to complements. Thus these logical operations preserve the property of being a Borel formula.



            It is implicit in the hypotheses that $Gamma$ acts by Borel automorphisms. Since $preceq$ is Borel, it follows that the predicate $gamma x prec x$ is Borel for any $gamma in Gamma$. The set $V$ can be defined as $$x in W: (not exists)(gamma in Gamma)((gamma x in W) wedge (gamma x prec x))$$.






            share|cite|improve this answer











            $endgroup$












            • $begingroup$
              Nice proof, thank you! One point remains non-obvious for me: "Since $preceq$ is Borel, the set $V$ consisting of the $preceq$-least element of each such set $mathcalO cap W$ is Borel." Could you elaborate on this?
              $endgroup$
              – Ilia Smilga
              4 hours ago











            • $begingroup$
              I responded as an edit to the answer.
              $endgroup$
              – burtonpeterj
              3 hours ago













            4












            4








            4





            $begingroup$

            The desired statement is entirely measure-theoretic, so it's not really necessary to think about the topology of $X$. By standard descriptive set theory, there exists a Borel linear ordering $preceq$ on $X$. (This means that the graph of $preceq$ is a Borel subset of $X times X$.)



            Suppose toward a contradiction that $mu$ is nonatomic and the $Gamma$-action is ergodic but that there exists a wandering set $W$ of positive measure. Without loss of generality we may assume that the intersection of every $Gamma$-orbit with $W$ is finite. The ordering $preceq$ restricts to a linear ordering on each $Gamma$-orbit. If a $Gamma$-orbit $mathcalO$ intersects $W$ then $mathcalO cap W$ is nonempty and finite, so that the $preceq$-least element of $mathcalO cap W$ is well-defined. Since $preceq$ is Borel, the set $V$ consisting of the $preceq$-least element of each such set $mathcalO cap W$ is Borel. The set $V$ contains at most one point from each $Gamma$-orbit. Since $W subseteq bigcup_gamma in Gamma V$ and $mu$ is $Gamma$-quasi-invariant it follows that $mu(V) > 0$.



            Since $mu$ is nonatomic, there exists a Borel set $V_1 subseteq V$ such that if we write $V_2 = V setminus V_1$ then $min(mu(V_1),mu(V_2)) > 0$. Let $widetildeV_j = bigcup_gamma in Gamma gamma V_j$. For each $j in 1,2$ the set $widetildeV_j$ is $Gamma$-invariant and since $widetildeV_j$ contains $V_j$ we have $mu(widetildeV_j) > 0$. By ergodicity it follows that $mu(X setminus widetildeV_j) = 0$ for each $j in 1,2$.



            We claim that $widetildeV_1$ and $widetildeV_2$ are pairwise disjoint, which will lead to the contradiction $$0 < mu(widetildeV_2) leq mu(X setminus widetildeV_1) =0$$



            We will establish the claim by showing that that existence of $x in widetildeV_1 cap widetildeV_2$ leads to a further contradiction. Suppose that there exists such a point $x$. Then there exist $gamma_1,gamma_2 in Gamma$ with $gamma_1x in V_1$ and $gamma_2x in V_2$. Since $V_1 cap V_2 = emptyset$ we have $gamma_1x neq gamma_2x$. Since $gamma_1x = gamma_1gamma_2^-1gamma_2x$ we see that $gamma_1x$ and $gamma_2x$ are in the same $Gamma$-orbit. This cannot be the case since $gamma_1x$ and $gamma_2x$ are both elements of $V$ and $V$ contains at most one point from each $Gamma$-orbit.



            $mathbfResponse,, to ,,comment$



            The way to see that the set $V$ is Borel is to regard Borel sets as being defined by logical formulas. We say that a formula 'is Borel' if it defines a Borel subset of $X$. Countable existential quantifiers correspond to countable unions and not corresponds to complements. Thus these logical operations preserve the property of being a Borel formula.



            It is implicit in the hypotheses that $Gamma$ acts by Borel automorphisms. Since $preceq$ is Borel, it follows that the predicate $gamma x prec x$ is Borel for any $gamma in Gamma$. The set $V$ can be defined as $$x in W: (not exists)(gamma in Gamma)((gamma x in W) wedge (gamma x prec x))$$.






            share|cite|improve this answer











            $endgroup$



            The desired statement is entirely measure-theoretic, so it's not really necessary to think about the topology of $X$. By standard descriptive set theory, there exists a Borel linear ordering $preceq$ on $X$. (This means that the graph of $preceq$ is a Borel subset of $X times X$.)



            Suppose toward a contradiction that $mu$ is nonatomic and the $Gamma$-action is ergodic but that there exists a wandering set $W$ of positive measure. Without loss of generality we may assume that the intersection of every $Gamma$-orbit with $W$ is finite. The ordering $preceq$ restricts to a linear ordering on each $Gamma$-orbit. If a $Gamma$-orbit $mathcalO$ intersects $W$ then $mathcalO cap W$ is nonempty and finite, so that the $preceq$-least element of $mathcalO cap W$ is well-defined. Since $preceq$ is Borel, the set $V$ consisting of the $preceq$-least element of each such set $mathcalO cap W$ is Borel. The set $V$ contains at most one point from each $Gamma$-orbit. Since $W subseteq bigcup_gamma in Gamma V$ and $mu$ is $Gamma$-quasi-invariant it follows that $mu(V) > 0$.



            Since $mu$ is nonatomic, there exists a Borel set $V_1 subseteq V$ such that if we write $V_2 = V setminus V_1$ then $min(mu(V_1),mu(V_2)) > 0$. Let $widetildeV_j = bigcup_gamma in Gamma gamma V_j$. For each $j in 1,2$ the set $widetildeV_j$ is $Gamma$-invariant and since $widetildeV_j$ contains $V_j$ we have $mu(widetildeV_j) > 0$. By ergodicity it follows that $mu(X setminus widetildeV_j) = 0$ for each $j in 1,2$.



            We claim that $widetildeV_1$ and $widetildeV_2$ are pairwise disjoint, which will lead to the contradiction $$0 < mu(widetildeV_2) leq mu(X setminus widetildeV_1) =0$$



            We will establish the claim by showing that that existence of $x in widetildeV_1 cap widetildeV_2$ leads to a further contradiction. Suppose that there exists such a point $x$. Then there exist $gamma_1,gamma_2 in Gamma$ with $gamma_1x in V_1$ and $gamma_2x in V_2$. Since $V_1 cap V_2 = emptyset$ we have $gamma_1x neq gamma_2x$. Since $gamma_1x = gamma_1gamma_2^-1gamma_2x$ we see that $gamma_1x$ and $gamma_2x$ are in the same $Gamma$-orbit. This cannot be the case since $gamma_1x$ and $gamma_2x$ are both elements of $V$ and $V$ contains at most one point from each $Gamma$-orbit.



            $mathbfResponse,, to ,,comment$



            The way to see that the set $V$ is Borel is to regard Borel sets as being defined by logical formulas. We say that a formula 'is Borel' if it defines a Borel subset of $X$. Countable existential quantifiers correspond to countable unions and not corresponds to complements. Thus these logical operations preserve the property of being a Borel formula.



            It is implicit in the hypotheses that $Gamma$ acts by Borel automorphisms. Since $preceq$ is Borel, it follows that the predicate $gamma x prec x$ is Borel for any $gamma in Gamma$. The set $V$ can be defined as $$x in W: (not exists)(gamma in Gamma)((gamma x in W) wedge (gamma x prec x))$$.







            share|cite|improve this answer














            share|cite|improve this answer



            share|cite|improve this answer








            edited 3 hours ago

























            answered 4 hours ago









            burtonpeterjburtonpeterj

            791413




            791413











            • $begingroup$
              Nice proof, thank you! One point remains non-obvious for me: "Since $preceq$ is Borel, the set $V$ consisting of the $preceq$-least element of each such set $mathcalO cap W$ is Borel." Could you elaborate on this?
              $endgroup$
              – Ilia Smilga
              4 hours ago











            • $begingroup$
              I responded as an edit to the answer.
              $endgroup$
              – burtonpeterj
              3 hours ago
















            • $begingroup$
              Nice proof, thank you! One point remains non-obvious for me: "Since $preceq$ is Borel, the set $V$ consisting of the $preceq$-least element of each such set $mathcalO cap W$ is Borel." Could you elaborate on this?
              $endgroup$
              – Ilia Smilga
              4 hours ago











            • $begingroup$
              I responded as an edit to the answer.
              $endgroup$
              – burtonpeterj
              3 hours ago















            $begingroup$
            Nice proof, thank you! One point remains non-obvious for me: "Since $preceq$ is Borel, the set $V$ consisting of the $preceq$-least element of each such set $mathcalO cap W$ is Borel." Could you elaborate on this?
            $endgroup$
            – Ilia Smilga
            4 hours ago





            $begingroup$
            Nice proof, thank you! One point remains non-obvious for me: "Since $preceq$ is Borel, the set $V$ consisting of the $preceq$-least element of each such set $mathcalO cap W$ is Borel." Could you elaborate on this?
            $endgroup$
            – Ilia Smilga
            4 hours ago













            $begingroup$
            I responded as an edit to the answer.
            $endgroup$
            – burtonpeterj
            3 hours ago




            $begingroup$
            I responded as an edit to the answer.
            $endgroup$
            – burtonpeterj
            3 hours ago











            1












            $begingroup$

            First a general comment. Unfortunately, the categorical approach is completely missing in the way the measure theory is still taught nowadays, and the fact that there actually is only one "reasonable" purely non-atomic probability measure space (so called Lebesgue, Lebesgue--Rokhlin, or standard probability space) isomorphic to the unit interval endowed with the classical Lebesgue measure is not very widely known. Any Borel probability measure on a Polish space makes it a Lebesgue space, so that in particular all measure spaces one has to deal with in the Patterson theory are from this class.



            The definition of a wandering set you are using is a non-standard one. According to the usual definition a measurable set is wandering if all its translates are pairwise disjoint mod 0 (i.e., the intersection with almost any orbit consists of at most one point). However, it is very easy to see that the existence of a wandering set $W$ in your sense implies the existence of a "usual" wandering set $W'$. Namely, realize your measure space as the unit interval, and then for each orbit take the minimal point from its intersection with $W$. This operation is clearly measurable and provides you with a measurable set $W'subset W$, which is wandering in the usual sense.



            You are asking why ergodicity implies complete conservativity. The reason (with the right definition of wandering sets) is very simple: the union of the translates of any non-trivial subset of a wandering set is obviously a non-trivial invariant set. Actually, more generally, the union of the free discrete ergodic components of the action is precisely the dissipative part of the Hopf decomposition. See Kaimanovich for more details and Grigorchuk - Kaimanovich - Nagnibeda for various examples concerning the relationship between dissipativity and minimality of boundary actions.






            share|cite|improve this answer









            $endgroup$

















              1












              $begingroup$

              First a general comment. Unfortunately, the categorical approach is completely missing in the way the measure theory is still taught nowadays, and the fact that there actually is only one "reasonable" purely non-atomic probability measure space (so called Lebesgue, Lebesgue--Rokhlin, or standard probability space) isomorphic to the unit interval endowed with the classical Lebesgue measure is not very widely known. Any Borel probability measure on a Polish space makes it a Lebesgue space, so that in particular all measure spaces one has to deal with in the Patterson theory are from this class.



              The definition of a wandering set you are using is a non-standard one. According to the usual definition a measurable set is wandering if all its translates are pairwise disjoint mod 0 (i.e., the intersection with almost any orbit consists of at most one point). However, it is very easy to see that the existence of a wandering set $W$ in your sense implies the existence of a "usual" wandering set $W'$. Namely, realize your measure space as the unit interval, and then for each orbit take the minimal point from its intersection with $W$. This operation is clearly measurable and provides you with a measurable set $W'subset W$, which is wandering in the usual sense.



              You are asking why ergodicity implies complete conservativity. The reason (with the right definition of wandering sets) is very simple: the union of the translates of any non-trivial subset of a wandering set is obviously a non-trivial invariant set. Actually, more generally, the union of the free discrete ergodic components of the action is precisely the dissipative part of the Hopf decomposition. See Kaimanovich for more details and Grigorchuk - Kaimanovich - Nagnibeda for various examples concerning the relationship between dissipativity and minimality of boundary actions.






              share|cite|improve this answer









              $endgroup$















                1












                1








                1





                $begingroup$

                First a general comment. Unfortunately, the categorical approach is completely missing in the way the measure theory is still taught nowadays, and the fact that there actually is only one "reasonable" purely non-atomic probability measure space (so called Lebesgue, Lebesgue--Rokhlin, or standard probability space) isomorphic to the unit interval endowed with the classical Lebesgue measure is not very widely known. Any Borel probability measure on a Polish space makes it a Lebesgue space, so that in particular all measure spaces one has to deal with in the Patterson theory are from this class.



                The definition of a wandering set you are using is a non-standard one. According to the usual definition a measurable set is wandering if all its translates are pairwise disjoint mod 0 (i.e., the intersection with almost any orbit consists of at most one point). However, it is very easy to see that the existence of a wandering set $W$ in your sense implies the existence of a "usual" wandering set $W'$. Namely, realize your measure space as the unit interval, and then for each orbit take the minimal point from its intersection with $W$. This operation is clearly measurable and provides you with a measurable set $W'subset W$, which is wandering in the usual sense.



                You are asking why ergodicity implies complete conservativity. The reason (with the right definition of wandering sets) is very simple: the union of the translates of any non-trivial subset of a wandering set is obviously a non-trivial invariant set. Actually, more generally, the union of the free discrete ergodic components of the action is precisely the dissipative part of the Hopf decomposition. See Kaimanovich for more details and Grigorchuk - Kaimanovich - Nagnibeda for various examples concerning the relationship between dissipativity and minimality of boundary actions.






                share|cite|improve this answer









                $endgroup$



                First a general comment. Unfortunately, the categorical approach is completely missing in the way the measure theory is still taught nowadays, and the fact that there actually is only one "reasonable" purely non-atomic probability measure space (so called Lebesgue, Lebesgue--Rokhlin, or standard probability space) isomorphic to the unit interval endowed with the classical Lebesgue measure is not very widely known. Any Borel probability measure on a Polish space makes it a Lebesgue space, so that in particular all measure spaces one has to deal with in the Patterson theory are from this class.



                The definition of a wandering set you are using is a non-standard one. According to the usual definition a measurable set is wandering if all its translates are pairwise disjoint mod 0 (i.e., the intersection with almost any orbit consists of at most one point). However, it is very easy to see that the existence of a wandering set $W$ in your sense implies the existence of a "usual" wandering set $W'$. Namely, realize your measure space as the unit interval, and then for each orbit take the minimal point from its intersection with $W$. This operation is clearly measurable and provides you with a measurable set $W'subset W$, which is wandering in the usual sense.



                You are asking why ergodicity implies complete conservativity. The reason (with the right definition of wandering sets) is very simple: the union of the translates of any non-trivial subset of a wandering set is obviously a non-trivial invariant set. Actually, more generally, the union of the free discrete ergodic components of the action is precisely the dissipative part of the Hopf decomposition. See Kaimanovich for more details and Grigorchuk - Kaimanovich - Nagnibeda for various examples concerning the relationship between dissipativity and minimality of boundary actions.







                share|cite|improve this answer












                share|cite|improve this answer



                share|cite|improve this answer










                answered 1 hour ago









                R WR W

                10.8k22050




                10.8k22050



























                    draft saved

                    draft discarded
















































                    Thanks for contributing an answer to MathOverflow!


                    • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

                    But avoid


                    • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

                    • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.

                    Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


                    To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




                    draft saved


                    draft discarded














                    StackExchange.ready(
                    function ()
                    StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmathoverflow.net%2fquestions%2f330010%2fergodic-without-atoms-implies-completely-conservative%23new-answer', 'question_page');

                    );

                    Post as a guest















                    Required, but never shown





















































                    Required, but never shown














                    Required, but never shown












                    Required, but never shown







                    Required, but never shown

































                    Required, but never shown














                    Required, but never shown












                    Required, but never shown







                    Required, but never shown







                    Popular posts from this blog

                    یوتیوب محتویات پیشینه[ویرایش] فناوری‌های ویدئویی[ویرایش] شوخی‌های آوریل[ویرایش] سانسور و فیلترینگ[ویرایش] آمار و ارقامی از یوتیوب[ویرایش] تأثیر اجتماعی[ویرایش] سیاست اجتماعی[ویرایش] نمودارها[ویرایش] یادداشت‌ها[ویرایش] پانویس[ویرایش] پیوند به بیرون[ویرایش] منوی ناوبریبررسی شده‌استYouTube.com[بروزرسانی]"Youtube.com Site Info""زبان‌های یوتیوب""Surprise! There's a third YouTube co-founder"سایت یوتیوب برای چندمین بار در ایران فیلتر شدنسخهٔ اصلیسالار کمانگر جوان آمریکایی ایرانی الاصل مدیر سایت یوتیوب شدنسخهٔ اصلیVideo websites pop up, invite postingsthe originalthe originalYouTube: Overnight success has sparked a backlashthe original"Me at the zoo"YouTube serves up 100 million videos a day onlinethe originalcomScore Releases May 2010 U.S. Online Video Rankingsthe originalYouTube hits 4 billion daily video viewsthe originalYouTube users uploading two days of video every minutethe originalEric Schmidt, Princeton Colloquium on Public & Int'l Affairsthe original«Streaming Dreams»نسخهٔ اصلیAlexa Traffic Rank for YouTube (three month average)the originalHelp! YouTube is killing my business!the originalUtube sues YouTubethe originalGoogle closes $A2b YouTube dealthe originalFlash moves on to smart phonesthe originalYouTube HTML5 Video Playerنسخهٔ اصلیYouTube HTML5 Video Playerthe originalGoogle tries freeing Web video with WebMthe originalVideo length for uploadingthe originalYouTube caps video lengths to reduce infringementthe originalAccount Types: Longer videosthe originalYouTube bumps video limit to 15 minutesthe originalUploading large files and resumable uploadingthe originalVideo Formats: File formatsthe originalGetting Started: File formatsthe originalThe quest for a new video codec in Flash 8the originalAdobe Flash Video File Format Specification Version 10.1the originalYouTube Mobile goes livethe originalYouTube videos go HD with a simple hackthe originalYouTube now supports 4k-resolution videosthe originalYouTube to get high-def 1080p playerthe original«Approximate YouTube Bitrates»نسخهٔ اصلی«Bigger and Better: Encoding for YouTube 720p HD»نسخهٔ اصلی«YouTube's 1080p – Failure Depends on How You Look At It»نسخهٔ اصلیYouTube in 3Dthe originalYouTube in 3D?the originalYouTube 3D Videosthe originalYouTube adds a dimension, 3D goggles not includedthe originalYouTube Adds Stereoscopic 3D Video Support (And 3D Vision Support, Too)the original«Sharing YouTube Videos»نسخهٔ اصلی«Downloading videos from YouTube is not supported, except for one instance when it is permitted.»نسخهٔ اصلی«Terms of Use, 5.B»نسخهٔ اصلی«Some YouTube videos get download option»نسخهٔ اصلی«YouTube looks out for content owners, disables video ripping»«Downloading videos from YouTube is not supported, except for one instance when it is permitted.»نسخهٔ اصلی«YouTube Hopes To Boost Revenue With Video Downloads»نسخهٔ اصلی«YouTube Mobile»نسخهٔ اصلی«YouTube Live on Apple TV Today; Coming to iPhone on June 29»نسخهٔ اصلی«Goodbye Flash: YouTube mobile goes HTML5 on iPhone and Android»نسخهٔ اصلی«YouTube Mobile Goes HTML5, Video Quality Beats Native Apps Hands Down»نسخهٔ اصلی«TiVo Getting YouTube Streaming Today»نسخهٔ اصلی«YouTube video comes to Wii and PlayStation 3 game consoles»نسخهٔ اصلی«Coming Up Next... YouTube on Your TV»نسخهٔ اصلی«Experience YouTube XL on the Big Screen»نسخهٔ اصلی«Xbox Live Getting Live TV, YouTube & Bing Voice Search»نسخهٔ اصلی«YouTube content locations»نسخهٔ اصلی«April fools: YouTube turns the world up-side-down»نسخهٔ اصلی«YouTube goes back to 1911 for April Fools' Day»نسخهٔ اصلی«Simon Cowell's bromance, the self-driving Nascar and Hungry Hippos for iPad... the best April Fools' gags»نسخهٔ اصلی"YouTube Announces It Will Shut Down""YouTube Adds Darude 'Sandstorm' Button To Its Videos For April Fools' Day"«Censorship fears rise as Iran blocks access to top websites»نسخهٔ اصلی«China 'blocks YouTube video site'»نسخهٔ اصلی«YouTube shut down in Morocco»نسخهٔ اصلی«Thailand blocks access to YouTube»نسخهٔ اصلی«Ban on YouTube lifted after deal»نسخهٔ اصلی«Google's Gatekeepers»نسخهٔ اصلی«Turkey goes into battle with Google»نسخهٔ اصلی«Turkey lifts two-year ban on YouTube»نسخهٔ اصلیسانسور در ترکیه به یوتیوب رسیدلغو فیلترینگ یوتیوب در ترکیه«Pakistan blocks YouTube website»نسخهٔ اصلی«Pakistan lifts the ban on YouTube»نسخهٔ اصلی«Pakistan blocks access to YouTube in internet crackdown»نسخهٔ اصلی«Watchdog urges Libya to stop blocking websites»نسخهٔ اصلی«YouTube»نسخهٔ اصلی«Due to abuses of religion, customs Emirates, YouTube is blocked in the UAE»نسخهٔ اصلی«Google Conquered The Web - An Ultimate Winner»نسخهٔ اصلی«100 million videos are viewed daily on YouTube»نسخهٔ اصلی«Harry and Charlie Davies-Carr: Web gets taste for biting baby»نسخهٔ اصلی«Meet YouTube's 224 million girl, Natalie Tran»نسخهٔ اصلی«YouTube to Double Down on Its 'Channel' Experiment»نسخهٔ اصلی«13 Some Media Companies Choose to Profit From Pirated YouTube Clips»نسخهٔ اصلی«Irate HK man unlikely Web hero»نسخهٔ اصلی«Web Guitar Wizard Revealed at Last»نسخهٔ اصلی«Charlie bit my finger – again!»نسخهٔ اصلی«Lowered Expectations: Web Redefines 'Quality'»نسخهٔ اصلی«YouTube's 50 Greatest Viral Videos»نسخهٔ اصلیYouTube Community Guidelinesthe original«Why did my YouTube account get closed down?»نسخهٔ اصلی«Why do I have a sanction on my account?»نسخهٔ اصلی«Is YouTube's three-strike rule fair to users?»نسخهٔ اصلی«Viacom will sue YouTube for $1bn»نسخهٔ اصلی«Mediaset Files EUR500 Million Suit Vs Google's YouTube»نسخهٔ اصلی«Premier League to take action against YouTube»نسخهٔ اصلی«YouTube law fight 'threatens net'»نسخهٔ اصلی«Google must divulge YouTube log»نسخهٔ اصلی«Google Told to Turn Over User Data of YouTube»نسخهٔ اصلی«US judge tosses out Viacom copyright suit against YouTube»نسخهٔ اصلی«Google and Viacom: YouTube copyright lawsuit back on»نسخهٔ اصلی«Woman can sue over YouTube clip de-posting»نسخهٔ اصلی«YouTube loses court battle over music clips»نسخهٔ اصلیYouTube to Test Software To Ease Licensing Fightsthe original«Press Statistics»نسخهٔ اصلی«Testing YouTube's Audio Content ID System»نسخهٔ اصلی«Content ID disputes»نسخهٔ اصلیYouTube Community Guidelinesthe originalYouTube criticized in Germany over anti-Semitic Nazi videosthe originalFury as YouTube carries sick Hillsboro video insultthe originalYouTube attacked by MPs over sex and violence footagethe originalAl-Awlaki's YouTube Videos Targeted by Rep. Weinerthe originalYouTube Withdraws Cleric's Videosthe originalYouTube is letting users decide on terrorism-related videosthe original«Time's Person of the Year: You»نسخهٔ اصلی«Our top 10 funniest YouTube comments – what are yours?»نسخهٔ اصلی«YouTube's worst comments blocked by filter»نسخهٔ اصلی«Site Info YouTube»نسخهٔ اصلیوبگاه YouTubeوبگاه موبایل YouTubeوووووو

                    Magento 2 - Auto login with specific URL Planned maintenance scheduled April 23, 2019 at 23:30 UTC (7:30pm US/Eastern) Announcing the arrival of Valued Associate #679: Cesar Manara Unicorn Meta Zoo #1: Why another podcast?Customer can't login - Page refreshes but nothing happensCustom Login page redirectURL to login with redirect URL after completionCustomer login is case sensitiveLogin with phone number or email address - Magento 1.9Magento 2: Set Customer Account Confirmation StatusCustomer auto connect from URLHow to call customer login form in the custom module action magento 2?Change of customer login error message magento2Referrer URL in modal login form

                    Rest API with Magento using PHP with example. Planned maintenance scheduled April 17/18, 2019 at 00:00UTC (8:00pm US/Eastern) Announcing the arrival of Valued Associate #679: Cesar Manara Unicorn Meta Zoo #1: Why another podcast?How to update product using magento client library for PHP?Oauth Error while extending Magento Rest APINot showing my custom api in wsdl(url) and web service list?Using Magento API(REST) via IXMLHTTPRequest COM ObjectHow to login in Magento website using REST APIREST api call for Guest userMagento API calling using HTML and javascriptUse API rest media management by storeView code (admin)Magento REST API Example ErrorsHow to log all rest api calls in magento2?How to update product using magento client library for PHP?